|
|||||
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
LESSON
06
MORAL
RESPONSIBILITY AND BLAME
Moral
Responsibility and Blame
Moral
responsibility is directed not
only at judgments concerning
right or wrong. Sometimes,
they
are directed at determining
whether a person or organization is
morally responsible
for
having
done something wrong. People
are not always responsible
for their wrongful or
injurious
acts: moral responsibility is incurred
only when a person knowingly and
freely acts in
an
immoral way or fails to act in a
moral way.
Ignorance
and inability to do otherwise are
two conditions, called
excusing
conditions, that
completely
eliminate a person's moral
responsibility for causing
wrongful injury. Ignorance
and
inability
do not always excuse a person, however.
When one deliberately keeps
oneself
ignorant
to escape responsibility, that
ignorance does not excuse
the wrongful injury. A
person
is
morally responsible for an
injury or a wrong if:
1.
The person caused or helped
cause it, or failed to
prevent it when he could and
should have;
2.
The person did so knowing
what he or she was
doing;
3.
The person did so of his own
free will.
Ignorance
may concern the relevant
facts or the relevant moral
standards. Generally, ignorance
of
the facts eliminates moral
responsibility. This is because
moral responsibility
requires
freedom,
which is impossible in the
case of ignorance of the
relevant facts. Inability
eliminates
responsibility
because a person cannot have a
moral obligation to do something
over which he
or
she has no control. A person is NOT
morally responsible for an
injury or a wrong if:
1.
The person did not cause and
could not prevent the
injury or wrong;
2.
The person did not know he
was inflicting the injury or
the wrong;
3.
The person did not inflict
the injury or the wrong of
his own free
will;
In
addition to the excusing
conditions, there are also
three mitigating factors
that diminish
moral
responsibility. They are:
1.
Circumstances that leave a person
uncertain (but not unsure)
about what he or she
is
doing;
2.
Circumstances that make it difficult
(but not impossible) for
the person to avoid doing
it;
3.
Circumstances that minimize
(but do not remove) a
person's involvement in an
act.
The
extents to which these
mitigating circumstances can diminish an
agent's responsibility
depend
on the seriousness of the
injury. Generally, the more
serious the injury, the less
the
mitigating
circumstances will diminish
responsibility.
We
begin with a discussion of apartheid-era
South Africa and Caltex, an
American oil
company
operating in South Africa
during that time. A large
number of Caltex
stockholders
opposed
the company's operations in
South Africa, and introduced a
series of shareholder
resolutions
requiring Caltex to leave
South Africa, which they saw
as racist and immoral.
Caltex's
management did not agree.
Rather than focusing on the
financial assistance they
were
giving
the South African
government, they pointed to
the positive effects their
operations had
on
black workers.
12
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
South
African leaders, such as Archbishop
Desmond Tutu, were not
convinced by Caltex's
arguments.
He supported the shareholder
resolutions, saying that
comfort under an
immoral
regime
was not preferable to freedom,
even at the cost of economic
hardship.
The
point of this example is to
show how a real moral
debate in business works.
The arguments
on
both sides appealed to moral
considerations and four basic
types of moral standards:
utilitarianism,
rights, justice, and caring.
The shareholders' argument
referred to the
unjust
policies
of the apartheid government and
the fact that these
policies violated the civil
rights of
black
citizens. On the other side,
Caltex's management made utilitarian
arguments and
arguments
about caring: it was in blacks'
best interests to have
Caltex jobs, and Caltex had
a
duty
to take care of these workers as
best it could. In addition,
both sides refer to the
moral
character
of the groups involved, basing
these distinctions on what is
called the ethic of
virtue.
The
following sections of this chapter
explain each of these
approaches, identifying
their
strengths
and weaknesses and showing how
they can be used to clarify
the moral issues we
confront
in business.
Utilitarianism:
Weighing Social Costs and
Benefits
Utilitarianism
(or consequentialism) characterizes the
moral approach taken by
Caltex's
management.
Another example, Ford and
its infamous Pinto, demonstrates
just how closely
the
weighing
of costs and benefits can be
done.
Ford
knew that the Pinto
would explode when rear-ended at
only 20 mph, but they also
knew
that
it would cost $137 million to fix the
problem. Since they would
only have to pay $49
million
in damages to injured victims and
the families of those who
died, they calculated that
it
was
not right to spend the
money to fix the cars when
society set such a low
price on the lives
and
health of the victims. The
kind of analysis that Ford
managers used in their
cost-benefit
study
is a version of what has
been traditionally called
utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism
is
a
general
term for any view
that holds that actions and
policies should be evaluated on
the basis
of
the benefits and costs they
will impose on society. In any situation,
the "right" action or
policy
is the one that will produce
the greatest net benefits or
the lowest net costs
(when all
alternatives
have only net costs).
Many
businesses rely on such
utilitarian cost-benefit analyses, and
maintain that the
socially
responsible
course to take is the utilitarian one
with the lowest net
costs.
Jeremy
Bentham founded traditional
utilitarianism. His version of
the theory assumes that
we
can
measure and add the
quantities of benefits produced by an
action and subtract the
measured
quantities
of harm it will cause, allowing us to
determine which action has
the most benefits or
lowest
total costs and is therefore
moral. The utility Bentham
had in mind was not the
greatest
benefit
for the person taking the
action, but rather the
greatest benefit for all
involved. For
Bentham:
"An
action is right from an
ethical point of view if and
only if the sum total
of
utilities
produced by that act is greater than
the sum total of utilities
produced by
any
other act the agent could
have performed in its
place."
Also,
it is important to note that
only one action can have the
lowest net costs and
greatest net
benefits.
13
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
To
determine what the moral
thing to do on any particular occasion
might be, there are
three
considerations
to follow:
1.
You must determine what
alternative actions are
available.
2.
You must estimate the direct and
indirect costs and benefits
the action would
produce
for
all involved in the
foreseeable future.
3.
You must choose the
alternative that produces the
greatest sum total of
utility.
Utilitarianism
is attractive to many because it matches
the views we tend to hold
when
discussing
governmental policies and public goods.
Most people agree, for
example, that when
the
government is trying to determine on
which public projects it
should spend tax monies,
the
proper
course of action would be for it to adopt
those projects that objective studies
show will
provide
the greatest benefits for
the members of society at the least
cost. It also fits in with
the
intuitive
criteria that many employ
when discussing moral
conduct. Utilitarianism can
explain
why
we hold certain types of
activities, such as lying, to be
immoral: it is so because of
the
costly
effects it has in the long
run. However, traditional
utilitarian's would deny
that an action
of
a certain kind is always
either right or wrong.
Instead, each action would
have to be weighed
given
its particular circumstances.
Utilitarian views have also
been highly influential
in
economics.
A long line of economists,
beginning in the 19th
century, argued that
economic
behavior
could be explained by assuming
that human beings always
attempt to maximize
their
utility
and that the utilities of
commodities can be measured by the prices
people are willing to
pay
for them.
Utilitarianism
is also the basis of the
techniques of economic costbenefit
analysis. This
type
of
analysis is used to determine
the desirability of investing in a
project (such as a dam,
factory,
or
public park) by figuring
whether its present and future
economic benefits outweigh
its
present
and future economic costs. To calculate
these costs and benefits,
discounted monetary
prices
are estimated for all the
effects the project will
have on the present and
future
environment
and on present and future populations.
Finally, we can note that
utilitarianism fits
nicely
with a value that many
people prize: efficiency. Efficiency
can
mean different things to
different
people, but for many it
means operating in such a
way that one produces the
most one
can
with the resources at
hand.
14
Table of Contents:
|
|||||