|
|||||
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
LESSON
31
Because of
these problems, some contend
that utilitarianism cannot lead
our pollution control
policy.
Perhaps absolute bans on
pollution are more adequate.
Some writers even suggest
that
when
risk cannot be reliably estimated, it is
best to steer clear of such
projects. Others
maintain
that
we should identify those who will
bear the risks and take
steps to protect
them.
It
holds that until those
patterns of hierarchy and domination
are changed, we will be unable to
deal
with environmental crises. In a system of
hierarchy, one group holds
power over another
and
members of the superior group
are able to dominate those of the
inferior group and get
them
to serve their Many thinkers
have argued that the
environmental crises we face are
rooted
in
the social systems of hierarchy and
domination that characterize
our society. This view,
now
referred
to as social ecology, ends.
What literally defines
social ecology as "social" is
its
recognition
of the often overlooked fact
that nearly all our present
ecological problems
arise
from
deep-seated social problems.
Conversely, present ecological problems
cannot be clearly
understood,
much less resolved, without
resolutely dealing with
problems within society.
To
make
this point more concrete:
economic, ethnic, cultural, and gender
conflicts, among many
others,
lie at the core of the most
serious ecological dislocations we face
today--apart, to be
sure,
from those that are produced
by natural catastrophes.
If
this approach seems a bit
too "sociological" for those
environmentalists who
identify
ecological
problems with the
preservation of wildlife, wilderness, or
more broadly, with
"Gaia"
and
planetary "Oneness," it might be
sobering to consider certain
recent facts. The massive
oil
spill
by an Exxon tanker at Prince
William Sound, the extensive
deforestation of redwood
trees
by
the Maxxam Corporation, and
the proposed James Bay
hydroelectric project that
would
flood
vast areas of northern
Quebec's forests, to cite
only a few problems, should
remind us that
the
real battleground on which
the ecological future of the
planet will be decided is clearly
a
social
one.
Indeed,
to separate ecological problems
from social problems--or
even to play down or
give
token
recognition to this crucial
relationship-- would be to grossly
misconstrue the sources
of
the
growing environmental crisis.
The way human beings deal
with each other as social
beings
is
crucial to addressing the
ecological crisis. Unless we
clearly recognize this, we will
surely
fail
to see that the hierarchical
mentality and class relationships
that so thoroughly
permeate
society
give rise to the very idea
of dominating the natural
world.
Unless
we realize that the present
market society, structured
around the brutally
competitive
imperative
of "grow or die," is a thoroughly
impersonal, self-operating mechanism, we
will
falsely
tend to blame technology as
such or population growth as
such for
environmental
problems.
We will ignore their root
causes, such as trade for
profit, industrial expansion,
and
the
identification of "progress" with
corporate self-interest. In short, we
will tend to focus on
the
symptoms of a grim social
pathology rather than on the
pathology itself, and our
efforts will
be
directed toward limited goals
whose attainment is more
cosmetic than
curative.
While
some have questioned whether
social ecology has dealt
adequately with issues
of
spirituality,
it was, in fact, among the
earliest of contemporary ecologies to
call for a sweeping
change
in existing spiritual values.
Such a change would mean a far-reaching
transformation of
our
prevailing mentality of domination
into one of complementarity, in which we
would see
our
role in the natural world as
creative, supportive, and deeply
appreciative of the needs
of
nonhuman
life. In social ecology, a
truly natural spirituality centers on
the ability of an
70
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
awakened
humanity to function as moral
agents in diminishing needless
suffering, engaging in
ecological
restoration, and fostering an aesthetic
appreciation of natural evolution in
all its
fecundity
and diversity.
Thus
social ecology has never
eschewed the need for a
radically new spirituality or
mentality in
its
call for a collective effort
to change society. Indeed, as early as
1965, the first
public
statement
to advance the ideas of social
ecology concluded with the
injunction: "The cast
of
mind
that today organizes
differences among human and
other life-forms along
hierarchical
lines
of 'supremacy' or 'inferiority' will give
way to an outlook that deals
with diversity in an
ecological
manner--that is, according to an
ethics of complementarity."1 In such an
ethics,
human
beings would complement nonhuman beings
with their own capacities to
produce a
richer,
creative, and developmental whole-not as
a "dominant" species but as a
supportive one.
Although
this idea, expressed at
times as an appeal for the
"respiritization of the natural
world,"
recurs
throughout the literature of
social ecology, it should
not be mistaken for a
theology that
raises
a deity above the natural
world or that seeks to
discover one within it. The
spirituality
advanced
by social ecology is definitively
naturalistic (as one would
expect, given its
relation
to
ecology itself, which stems
from the biological sciences),
rather than supernaturalistic
or
pantheistic.
To
prioritize any form of
spirituality over the social
factors that actually erode
all forms of
spirituality,
raises serious questions about
one's ability to come to grips
with reality. At a
time
when
a blind social mechanism,
the market, is turning soil
into sand, covering fertile
land with
concrete,
poisoning air and water, and
producing sweeping climatic and
atmospheric changes,
we
cannot ignore the impact
that a hierarchical and class
society has on the natural
world. We
must
earnestly deal with the fact
that economic growth, gender oppressions,
and ethnic
domination-not
to speak of corporate, state, and
bureaucratic interests-are much more
capable
of
shaping the future of the
natural world than are
privatistic forms of spiritual
self-
regeneration.
These forms of domination must be
confronted by collective action and
major
social
movements that challenge the
social sources of the
ecological crisis, not
simply by
personalistic
forms of consumption and investment
that often go under the
rubric of "green
capitalism."
We live in a highly cooperative
society that is only too
eager to find new areas
of
commercial
aggrandizement and to add ecological
verbiage to its advertising and
customer
relations.
Until
these systems (such as racism,
sexism, and social classes)
are changed, we will be unable
to
deal adequately with the
environment. Eco-feminists, a related
group of thinkers, sees
the
key
form of hierarchy connected to
the destruction of the
environment as the domination
of
women
by men. They believe that
there are important
connections between the
domination of
women
and the domination of naturepatterns
of thinking, which justify and perpetuate
the
subordination.
This logic of domination
sets up dualisms (artificial and
natural, male and
female)
where one of the pair is
seen as stronger and more
important. To solve our
ecological
problems,
we must first change these
destructive modes of
thinking.
According
to the ethics of caring, the
destruction of nature that
has accompanied male
domination
must be replaced with caring
for and nurturing our
relationships with nature
and
other
living things. Nature must
be seen as an "other" that
must be cared for, not tamed
or
dominated.
Thought-provoking as these approaches
are, they are still
too new and
undeveloped
to
give us specific
direction.
71
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
The
Ethics of Conserving Depletable
Resources
Conservation
refers to the saving or
rationing of natural resources
for later use. In fact,
even
pollution
control can be seen as a form of
conservation, since pollution consumes
air and water.
However,
generally, conservation refers to
the saving of finite,
depletable resources. The
only
source
of such resources is what
has been left over
from previous
generations.
As
we deplete the world's resources, there
is unavoidably a smaller amount of
them left for
future
generations. If future generations
have an equal right to the
world's resources, then by
depleting
them we are stealing what is
actually theirs.
A
number of writers have
claimed that it is a mistake to
think that future
generations have
rights.
They advance three main
reasons to show this:
First,
future generations cannot
intelligently be said to have
rights because they do not
now
exist
and may never exist. I may
be able to think about future people,
but I cannot hit
them,
punish
them, injure them, or treat
them wrongly. Future people
exist only in the
imagination,
and
imaginary entities cannot be
acted on in any way
whatsoever except in the
imagination.
Similarly,
we cannot say that future people
possess things now when
they do not yet exist
to
possess
or have them. Because there
is a possibility that future
generations may never
exist,
they
cannot "possess"
rights.
Second,
if future generations did
have rights, we might be led
to the absurd conclusion that
we
must
sacrifice our entire
civilization for their sake.
Suppose that each of the
infinite number of
future
generations had an equal right to
the world's supply of oil.
Then we would have to
divide
the
oil equally among them
all, and our share would be
a few quarts at the most. We
would
then
be put in the absurd position of
having to shut down our
entire Western civilization so
that
each
future person might be able to possess a
few quarts of oil.
Third,
we can say that someone has a
certain right only if we
know that he or she has a
certain
interest
that that right protects.
The purpose of a right, after
all, is to protect the
interests of the
right
holder, but we are virtually
ignorant of what interests
future generations will have.
What
wants
will they have?
John
Rawls, on the other hand,
argues that though it is
unjust to impose heavy burdens
on
present
generations for the sake of
the future, it is also unjust
for present generations to leave
nothing
for the future. We should
ask ourselves what we can
reasonably expect they
might
want
and, putting ourselves in
their place, leave what we
would like them to have
left for us.
Justice,
in short, requires that we
hand over to our children a
world in no worse condition
than
the
one we received ourselves.
72
Table of Contents:
|
|||||