|
|||||
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
LESSON
17
FREE
MARKETS AND UTILITY: ADAM
SMITH
Smith's
utilitarian argument is most
commonly criticized for
making what some call
unrealistic
arguments.
First, Smith assumes that no
one seller can control the
price of a good. Though
this
may
have been true at one time,
today many industries are
monopolized to some
extent.
Second,
Smith assumes that the
manufacturer will pay for
all the resources used to
produce a
product,
but when a manufacturer uses
water and pollutes it without
cleaning it, for
example,
someone
else must pay to do so.
Third, Smith assumes that
humans are motivated only by
a
natural,
self-interested desire for
profit. This, say his
critics, is clearly false.
Many humans are
concerned
for others and act to help
others, constraining their
own self-interest.
Market
systems,
say Smith's critics, make humans
selfish and make us think that
the profit motive is
natural.
One
especially influential critic of
Smith was John Maynard
Keynes. Keynes argued
that
government
intervention was necessary because
there is a mismatch between
aggregate supply
and
demand, which inevitably leads to a
contraction of supply. Government,
according to
Keynes,
can influence the propensity to
save, which lowers aggregate
demand and creates
unemployment.
Government can prevent excess
savings through its
influence on interest rates,
and
it can influence interest rates by
regulating the money supply.
The higher the supply
of
money,
the lower the rate at which
it is lent. Second, government can
directly affect the
amount
of
money households have
available to them by raising or
lowering taxes. Third,
government
spending
can close any gap between
aggregate demand and aggregate supply by
taking up the
slack
in demand from households and businesses.
Keynes' arguments became
less convincing
after
the stagflation of the
1970s, though. It has been
replaced by a post-Keynesian school
of
thought,
which argues for even
more governmental intervention in
the market.
Social
Darwinists had a different take on the
utilitarian justification for
free markets. They
argued
that economic competition
produced human progress. If governments
were to interfere
in
this process, they would
also unintentionally be impeding human
progress. Weak firms
must
be
weeded out by competition,
they claim. The basic
problem underlying the views
of the
social
Darwinist, however, is the
fundamental normative assumption
that survival
of the fittest
means
survival
of the best. That
is, whatever results from
the workings of nature is
necessarily
good.
The fallacy, which modern
authors call the naturalistic
fallacy,
implies, of
course, that
whatever
happens naturally is always
for the best.
Free
Trade and Utility: David
Ricardo
Adam
Smith's major work, the
Wealth
of Nations, in fact, was
primarily aimed at showing
the
benefits
of free trade. There he
wrote:
It
is the maxim of every
prudent master of a family never to
attempt to make at
home
what it will cost him more to make
than to buy. The tailor
does not make his
own
shoes but buys them
from the shoemaker... What
is prudence in the conduct
of
every
family can scarce be folly in
that of a great kingdom. If a foreign
country can
supply
us with a commodity cheaper
than we ourselves can make it,
better buy it of
them
with some part of the
produce of our own industry,
employed in a way in
which
we have some advantage.
Adam
Smith's point here is simple.
Like individuals, countries
differ in their ability to
produce
goods.
One country can produce a good
more cheaply than another
and it is then said to
have
38
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
an
"absolute
advantage" in producing
that good. These cost differences
may be based on
differences
in labor costs and skills,
climate, technology, equipment,
land, or natural resources.
Suppose
that because of these
differences, our nation can make one
product for less than
a
foreign
nation can, and suppose the
foreign nation can make some
other product for less
than
we
can. Then clearly it would
be best for both nations to
specialize in making the
product each
has
an "absolute advantage" in producing, and
to trade it for what the
other country has an
"absolute
advantage" in producing. It was Ricardo's
genius to realize that both
countries could
benefit
from specialization and trade even
though one can make everything more
cheaply than
the
other. Specialization increases
the total output of goods
countries produce, and
through
trade
all countries can share in
this added bounty.
Ricardo's
ingenious argument has been
hailed as the single "most
important" and "most
meaningful"
economic discovery ever
made. Some have said it is
the most "surprising"
and
"counterintuitive"
concept in economics. It is,
without a doubt, the most
important concept in
international
trade theory today and is at the
heart of the most
significant economic
arguments
people
propose today when they
argue in favor of globalization. Ricardo
makes a number of
simplifying
assumptions that clearly do not
hold in the real world,
such as that there are
only
two
countries making only two
products with only a fixed
number of workers. But these
are
merely
simplifying assumptions Ricardo
made to get his point across
more easily and
Ricardo's
conclusion
could still be proved
without these
assumptions.
There
are other assumptions,
however, that are not so
easy to get around. First,
Ricardo
assumes
that the resources used to
produce goods (labor,
equipment, factories, etc.) do
not
move
from one country to another. Yet
today multinational companies can, and
easily do, move
their
productive capital from one
country to another. Second, Ricardo
assumes that each
country's
production costs are
constant and do not decline as
countries expand their
production
or
as they acquire new
technology.
Third,
Ricardo assumes that workers
can easily and unreservedly move
from one industry to
another.
Yet when a company closes
down because it cannot compete
with imports from
another
country that has a
comparative advantage in those goods, the
company's workers are
laid
off, suffer heavy costs,
need retraining, and often
cannot find comparable
jobs.
Finally,
and perhaps most importantly,
Ricardo ignores international
rule setters. International
trade
inevitably leads to disagreements and
conflicts, and so countries must
agree to abide by
some
set of rules and
rule-setters.
Marx
and Justice: Criticizing Markets and
Trade
Karl
Marx offers the most
critical view of modern
private property and free
market institutions.
Marx
claims that free-market
capitalism necessarily produces extremes
of inequality. Since
capitalist
systems offer only two
sources of incomeowning the
means of production and
selling
one's laborworkers cannot
produce anything without the
owner of the
productive
forces.
But owners do not pay
the full value of the
workers' labor; they pay
workers what they
need
to subsist, keeping the rest for
themselves and gradually becoming
wealthier as a result.
39
Table of Contents:
|
|||||