/
40-3_files/40-300001im.jpg" width="695" height="1066"
useMap="#Map">
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
LESSON
03
THEORY
OF ETHICAL RELATIVISM
Some
theorists maintain that
moral notions apply only to
individuals, not to
corporations
themselves.
They say that it makes no
sense to hold businesses
"responsible" since businesses
are
more like machines than
people. Others counter that
corporations do act like
individuals,
having
objectives and actions, which can be
moral or immoral just as an
individual's action
might
be.
In
2002, for example, the
Justice Department charged the accounting
firm of Arthur
Andersen
for
obstruction of justice. Arthur
Andersen was caught shredding
documents showing how
they
helped
Enron hide its debt through
the use of several
accounting tricks. Critics
afterward
claimed
that the Justice Department
should have charged the
individual employees of
Arthur
Andersen,
not the company, because
"Companies don't commit
crimes, people do."
Perhaps
neither extreme view is
correct. Corporate actions do
depend on human
individuals
who
should be held accountable
for their actions. However,
they also have policies and
culture
that
direct individuals, and should
therefore be held accountable
for the effects of
these
corporate
artifacts.
Nonetheless,
it makes perfectly good sense to say
that a corporate organization
has moral duties
and
that it is morally responsible
for its acts. However,
organizations have moral
duties and are
morally
responsible in a secondary sense; a
corporation has a moral duty
to do something only
if
some of its members have a
moral duty to make sure it is done, and a
corporation is morally
responsible
for something only if some
of its members are morally
responsible for what
happened.
Virtually
all of the 500 largest U.S.
industrial corporations today
are multinationals.
Operating
in
more than one country at once produces a
new set of ethical dilemmas.
Multinationals can
escape
environmental regulations and labor
laws by shifting to another
country, for example.
They
can shift raw materials, goods, and
capital so that they escape
taxes. In addition,
because
they
have new technologies and
products that less developed
countries do not,
multinationals
must
decide when a particular
country is ready to assimilate
these new things. They
are also
faced
with the different moral
codes and laws of different
countries. Even if a particular
norm
is
not unethical, they must
still decide between
competing standards in their
many operations.
Ethical
relativism is the
theory that, because
different societies have different
ethical beliefs, there
is
no rational way of determining
whether an action is morally
right or wrong other than by
asking
whether
the people of this or that
society believe it to be right or wrong by asking
whether people of
a
particular society believe that it is. In
fact, the multiplicity of
moral codes demonstrates
that there
is
no one "right" answer to ethical
questions. The best a
company can do is follow the
old adage,
"When
in Rome, do as the Romans do." In other
words, there are no absolute
moral standards.
Cultural
relativism asserts
that morality varies from
one culture to another, since
similar
practices
are regarded as right in
some cultures and wrong in
others. However,
regarding
practices
as right or wrong does not
necessarily make them so,
nor does it exclude
the
possibility
of demonstrating that moral
beliefs are mistaken. For
this reason, cultural
relativism
does
not prohibit the possibility
of justification. Ethical
relativism, on the
other hand, makes
the
philosophical assertion that there is no
standard of right or wrong apart from
the morality of
a
culture. Whatever practices a culture
holds to be right is actually
right for that culture.
There
6
/
40-3_files/40-300002im.jpg" width="695" height="1066"
useMap="#Map">
Business
Ethics MGT610
VU
is
no possibility for justification
because there exists no standard
outside that culture.
Ethical
relativism
results in an uncritical acceptance of
all moral beliefs as equally
valid.
Critics
of ethical relativism point
out that it is illogical to
assume that because there is
more
than
one answer to an ethical question
that both answers are
equally correct ─
or even
that
either
answer is correct. They also
maintain that there are
more similarities than
differences
even
among what seem to be very
divergent societies.
The
late Philosopher James
Rachels put the matter
quite succinctly:
The
fact that different
societies have different
moral codes proves nothing.
There is also
disagreement
from society to society
about scientific matters: in
some cultures it is
believed
that
the earth is flat, and evil
spirits cause disease. We do
not on that account conclude
that
there
is no truth in geography or in medicine.
Instead, we conclude that in
some cultures people
are
better informed than in
others. Similarly, disagreement in ethics
might signal nothing
more
than
that some people are less
enlightened than others. At
the very least, the
fact of
disagreement
does not, by itself, entail
that truth does not
exist.
Why
should we assume that, if
ethical truth exists,
everyone must know
it?'
However,
the most telling criticisms
of the theory point out
that it has incoherent
consequences.
For
example, it becomes impossible to
criticize a practice of another
society as long as
members
of that society conform to
their own standards. How
could we maintain that
Nazi
Germany
or pre-Civil War Virginia
were wrong if we were
consistent relativists? There
must
be
criteria other than the
society's own moral
standards by which we can judge
actions in any
particular
society. Though we should
not dismiss the moral
beliefs of other cultures,
we
likewise
should not conclude that
all systems of morality are
equally acceptable.
Finally,
new technologies developed in
the closing decades of the
20th century and the
opening
years
of the 21st century are again
transforming society and business and
creating the
potential
for
new ethical problems. They
bring with them questions of
risks, which may be
unpredictable
and/or
irreversible. Who should
decide whether the benefits
of a particular technology
are
worth
the risks? How will victims of
bad technology be compensated for
their loss? How will
risk
be distributed? How will privacy be
maintained? How will property
rights be protected?
7